| |
Next: 12.2 Objective Actualisation -
Up: 12. Measurements and Other
Previous: 12. Measurements and Other
12.1 The Problem of Measurement
We have postponed until now the question of the exact prerequisites for
a measurement or actualising event to occur. This is because the question
of measurement is to some extent independent of the previous discussions.
Much of those discussions have been concerned about `what exists', whereas
the problem of measurement concerns which particular causal factors
influence the actualisation of propensities, that is, the `reduction of the wave
packet' of quantum mechanics.
Traditionally, the question of measurement in quantum world has been most
problematic. Because measurements seem to have effects on particular
quantum systems that are probabilistic, and are not described entirely by
Schrödinger's equation, they have given rise to many and varied
debates. Questions have been continually raised concerning some of the
deepest questions in philosophy, such as whether the world exists
independently of our observations or of our minds, whether physical
substances exist and/or have any definite properties, whether indeed
anything could be said to have definitely happened to the
exclusion of its alternatives. Many of these general questions
about the nature of reality have been answered by the general theory of
actualities and potentialities of this book, but there still remain many
specific questions concerning exactly when and how measurements
and other actualisations do occur.
In chapter
10,
actualisation was assumed to be a spontaneous mode of action of
propensities, whereby potentiality was transformed into an actuality at a
specific place in space and time, and whereby future potentialities were
restricted to take into account the consequences of that event having
definitely happened. It was pointed out that this function could be used
to replace the special category of measurements that had
been postulated in quantum theory ever since von Neumann [1929].
For measurements were also assumed to have definite outcomes without
equivocation, to be historically irreversible, and to be essentially
projections of the wave function at some time onto one of a
selection of eigenstates of some `measurement observable'. Von Neumann
called this process the reduction of the wave packet, and had to postulate
it separately from the time evolution governed by Schrödinger's
equation. In our philosophy of nature, however, it is to be
expected that propensities, as well as having forms of
distribution in space and time, also have a characteristic mode
of operation wherein some one possibility becomes actualised to the
exclusion of its competitors. Although quantum measurements can be
performed for any of a wide range of quantum variables, and actualisations
were assumed to be always point localisations in space-time, it was
argued, following Feyman and Hibbs [1965] and N. Maxwell [1976],
that arbitrary quantum mechanical measurement processes could always be
reduced to essentially a set of localisations in space and time.
In chapter
11,
however, it was pointed out that point localisations in
ordinary space and time are not acceptable, as they result in
completely indeterminate momenta and energy, and as they give
subsequent wave functions (propensity fields) which are not
largely selections of what was present before the measurement. Therefore,
the concept of point actualising was reconsidered, and found to refer to
point localisations in a tree-structured space of selections of branches
of the wave function.
In this way, we could more accurately follow what was
called the Principle of Selection: that the effects of the
actualisation are a selection of the field extent not only at the time of
the actualisation, but also at all subsequent times.
As it stands however, the Principle of Selection does not have a precisely
defined meaning, as it is not clear what does or does not constitute a
`selection' of a propensity field. It could be strictly interpreted, to
mean that no probability at any future spacetime point be
changed apart from the overall renormalisation that is necessary to bring
a whole branch to unit probability. This has the effect of ruling out any
actualisation that eliminates any interference terms that would otherwise
be present. It would only allow the selection of one of a set of branches
that were already disjoint, and had no overlaps or interference
possibilities of any kind. If particular actualising events could be made
to follow this strict rule, then the quantum measurement problem would be
solved entirely, though in a way which is perhaps too perfect. The
significance of this `perfection' will become apparent when we consider
various `imperfect' schemes later in this chapter. Those schemes will be
`imperfect' because there will be probability changes (following the
selection) that are not just overall renormalisations. As probability
changes are in principle observable, it should be possible to provide
empirical evidence either for or against them. That is, `imperfect
schemes' are not just interpretations which leave all predictions the
same, but are in fact individual physical theories with specific
experimental consequences.
A more serious criticism of basing physical laws on a strict Principle of
Selection, is that it makes present events depend on
propensities for all future times. They are of course
present potentialities, so the knowledge of the future that is
required is not the impossible `what will actually happen', but the more
feasible `what is allowed by propensities in the present state'. Still, it
does seem rather unusual to have `non-localities in time' of this kind. It
is as if nature automatically knew all possible consequences of its
present state, a knowledge denied to us mere mortals (but keenly sought
after by scientists and politicians). I am not denying that it is
logically possible, only that we should also consider conditions for
actualising that depend only on features of the present local region of
space and time. The remainder of this chapter will examine rules for
actualising of that kind, and see which are compatible with the philosophy
of nature that has been formulated so far.
There are two principal ways of having actualisations occur on the basis
of local features of the processes going on at that time. One way has the
actualising events prompted by certain physical conditions
pertaining at that time, and the other way has the actualising events
prompted by certain mental conditions pertaining at that time.
We could call these `objective actualising' and `mind-dependent
actualising' respectively, and various schemes for them will be considered
below.
You may be surprised that I am considering `mind-dependent' actualising at
all, as it seems to be counter to the main trend in my philosophy of
nature. I have tried to resolve the difficulties of quantum mechanics by
reformulating physics, rather than by introducing subjective elements,
by redefining the relation between theory and reality, or by having
consciousness `create reality' in some way. The fact that the physical world
exists objectively does not mean, however, that minds are logically
forbidden from existing objectively too. We are not committing ourselves
to subjectivism if we take other persons' minds to have real influences in
the world, as this would presumably be then a matter of fact, rather than
of subjective judgement. We have to consider this possibility (alongside
that of more mundane schemes), because many physicists and philosophers
(e.g. Wigner and Popper) have argued from the likelihood of
mind-dependent actualising to the reality (in some manner) of minds. One
purpose of this chapter is to examine precisely this likelihood
of mind-dependent actualising. It is by no means as likely as some people
would like to think: in the next section we will see that many
`objective' or mind-independent conditions can be proposed and made to
work, and more attention should be paid to these proposals.
Next: 12.2 Objective Actualisation -
Up: 12. Measurements and Other
Previous: 12. Measurements and Other
Prof Ian Thompson
2003-02-25
|