| |
Next: 2.3 Are Dispositions Real?
Up: 2. Dispositions
Previous: 2.1 Everyday Dispositions
2.2 Derivative Dispositions
Before examining in more detail the general features of dispositions, I
want time to explain the general idea of a `derivative disposition'. I
first show by examples what is meant by the term, and then examine how
such dispositions differ from `component dispositions'. This means that
they are not part of the prior disposition, but that they are
generated by action of the prior disposition in suitable circumstances.
Derivative dispositions are not very common in physical theories, the best
example being perhaps that of potential energy. Energy itself is kind of
disposition to interact in a certain way, so potential energy --
defined usually as `the ability to do work' -- is thus the
disposition to produce dispositions with specific values of kinetic
energy. The potential energy in a coiled spring, for example, is thus the
disposition to move the spring with certain velocities (kinetic energies),
and these movements of the spring are dispositions to interact in certain
ways with whatever is in its path.
Many more interesting examples of derivative dispositions can be found in
everyday life. They arise whenever the accomplishment of a given
disposition requires the operation of successive steps of kinds different
from the overall step. The original disposition on its operation therefore
generates from itself the `derived dispositions' for the
intermediate steps, which are means to the original end. An original
`disposition to learn', for example, can generate the derived
`disposition to read books', which can generate further
`dispositions to search for books'. These dispositions would then
generate dispositions to move one's body, which in turn lead ultimately
to one's limbs having (physical) dispositions to move. These
successively generated dispositions are all derived from the
original disposition to learn, according to the specific situations.
One example of original and derivative dispositions is the ability to
learn. To say that someone is easy to teach, or that they are musical, for
example, does not mean that there is any specific action that they are
capable of doing. Rather, it means that they well disposed to learn new
skills (whether of a musical or of a general kind), and that it is these
new skills that lead to specific actions.
Another example is of three `degrees' of derivative dispositions.
Swedenborg [1763] proposes that `conatus', force and motion form a series
of `discrete degrees' in living things, with force being derivative from
conatus, and motion from force.
It is known that conatus does nothing of itself, but acts through forces
corresponding to it, thereby producing motion; consequently that conatus
is the all in forces, and through forces is the all in motion; and since
motion is the outmost degree of conatus, through motion conatus exerts its
power. Conatus, force and motion are no otherwise conjoined than according
to degrees of height, conjunction of which is not by continuity, for they
are discrete, but by correspondences. For conatus is not force, nor is
force motion, but force is produced by conatus, because force is conatus
made active, and through force motion is produced; consequently there is
no power in conatus alone, nor in force alone, but in motion, which is
their product. That this is so may still seem doubtful, because not
illustrated by applications to sensible and perceptible things in nature:
nevertheless, such is the progression of conatus, force and motion into
power2.3.
Talk of derivative dispositions is taking the view, following Swedenborg
and more recently Broad [1925], that there are `levels' of causal
influence here. It allows that particular dispositions or intentions are
best regarded not as the most fundamental causes, but as `intermediate
stages' in the operation of more persistent `desires' and `motivations'.
The intention to find a book, for example, could be the product or
derivative of some more persistent `desire for reading', and need only be
produced in the appropriate circumstances. Broad would say that the
derived dispositions were the realisation of the underlying
dispositions.
In each particular case, there is clearly scope for many specific and
detailed investigations. The point is that whatever the details may be,
the `process logic' to be developed in this book can be applied at
each level or stage. This is because the process logic can be
applied both to the production of actual events, and also to the
production of further `derivative dispositions' at a `second stage'.
That such derivative dispositions can be formed means the
original disposition was not a simple disposition, but had some
complexity in its first appearance. However, the `disposition to search
for a book' is not strictly a component of a `disposition
to learn', in the sense of being always an actual part of
that disposition, as it is only derived in appropriate circumstances. For
this reason we talk of `derived' rather than `component'
dispositions, as the `disposition to learn' is not simply the mere
aggregate of all the dispositions that can be derived from it, just as any
disposition or cause is not merely an aggregate of all its possible
effects. Rather, the original disposition is more like a `higher
order' disposition to generate its derived dispositions according to
circumstances. Just as the effects of a disposition are not contained
within it, but are generated from it according to circumstances, so
derived dispositions are not contained within a higher-order disposition,
but are generated from it according to circumstances.
The notion of `derivative dispositions' will be used again in chapter
11.
Next: 2.3 Are Dispositions Real?
Up: 2. Dispositions
Previous: 2.1 Everyday Dispositions
Prof Ian Thompson
2003-02-25
|