| |
Next: 2.4 Scientific Explanation of
Up: 2. Dispositions
Previous: 2.2 Derivative Dispositions
2.3 Are Dispositions Real?
It seems that dispositions are real properties of the things which have
them. Before going on to look at the scientific explanation of
dispositions, I want to consider some possible philosophical reasons for
doubting the reality of dispositions. We might find force, for example,
in one or more of the following objections: (a) that one should deny the
subjunctive in the power ascription as anything more than hypothetical,
(b) science should be content with finding only the regularity of effects,
and not try to discover causes and determining constitutions, (c) that
causes are only (previous) events and not powers & dispositions, or (d) that
the world should be considered as a `Zeno universe' that has only
successive states and no proper changes.
Taking approach (a), Ryle ([1949], ch. 5) denies that dispositional ascriptions
`assert extra matters of fact' and claims that they are
only `inference-tickets, the minimal dispositions which
licence us to predict, retrodict, etc.' That is, he would omit any
`in virtue of the constitution of S' phrase in the meaning of
dispositions, and, in a sense, make dispositions strange kind of things
`no more substantial than a promise' (as Herbert [1985] puts it). Since
then, there is no property of S which makes the ascription true, that
truth cannot be explained by properties of S. Thus Ryle (quite explicitly)
denies that one should even look for either causal or mechanistic
explanations of the dispositions. Even, presumably, in cases in physics
and chemistry where there are quite obviously explanations in terms of
constituents and their propensities to attract and repel each other. His
restriction on looking for explanations in terms of internal dynamics is
largely disregarded in scientific practice.
Concerning injunction (b), I accept that all observations are of effects
rather than of causes, but that does not mean we cannot conceive of causes
and of the way they might lead to effects.
It seems to me quite legitimate for causes to be postulated in a Popperian
fashion, and the consequences deduced for the production of effects. The
reverse induction is quite different : obviously we cannot
deduce precise causes from observable effects (as Hume has long pointed
out), but that does not mean that there no causes.
It should not be necessary to accept Hume's [1739] conclusion that ``the
distinction, which we often make between a power and the exercise of it,
is without foundation''.
The attitude of (c) has been taken by Davidson [1967], when he argues that
causality is a two-place relation between individual events. Thus causal
relations are certainly not just implications from the description of the
first event to that of the second event, but are something more real. The
reality of causality, however, does not thereby automatically include such
components as dispositions and propensities,
although Steiner [1986] wants to extend Davidson's ideas in this
direction. I want to allow both dispositions and
previous events to be causes, although in different senses.
A distinction thus ought to be made between the `Principal Cause' (that
disposition which operates), and the `Instrumental Cause' (that
circumstance by means of which dispositions operate). Principal causes
operate according to instrumental causes. Both are necessary for any
event, for example, when a stone is let fall: the principal cause is the
earth's gravitational attraction, and the instrumental cause is our action
of letting go. Its hitting the ground is thus caused by our letting go,
but only as an instrumental cause. Many common uses of `cause' (including
that of Davidson [1967]) refer to instrumental causes rather than
principal causes, as it is only in the instrumental sense that
events can be said to be causes. Previous events cannot be
efficacious causes,
Emmet [1984] points out, in the sense of `producing' or `giving rise to'
their effects. Davidson would argue that that the `onslaught' (i.e. the
beginning) of a state or disposition is an event: `a desire to hurt your
feelings may spring up at the moment you anger me; I may start wanting to
eat a melon just when I see one.'2.4
That commencement event could then be regarded as the event which is the
cause of the effects of the dispositions and desires. The difficulty with
this argument is that only some, but not all, dispositions have initiating
events of this kind. It is difficult, for example, to pinpoint the events
which initiated the gravitational disposition of the earth, and the
solubility of salt. In these instances, as elsewhere, it makes more sense
to give a (principal) causal capacity to the dispositions themselves.
To consider (d) the world as a `block universe' or `Zeno universe', as
recently pointed out by Emmet [1984], is to see only different states of
affairs at successive times, and not to see the changes that lead to these
differences. Since the rise of Einsteinian relativity, it has become
popular to see all of time and space in one `block continuum' of four
dimensions, and to see change as only the difference between successive
`time slices' of this continuum. In this world there is only what actually
happens, and as in (a) above, what `might have happened' is purely
hypothetical. The only sense of `might happen' that can be invoked is to
imagine an entirely new possible world, e.g. one with different initial
conditions or different physical laws. This world view thus does not base
power ascriptions on any real features of this particular universe.
If we reject the `block universe' account of time, we are also rejecting
the view of time in which the future is `already formed' and perfectly
definite in advance of its happening, if indeed on this account anything
happens at all. (In extreme versions of this theory, time and real change
are both completely illusory,
but Grünbaum ([1973], ch. 10) shows
that more moderate positions can be held.) I admit that these accounts
have an internal consistency that makes them difficult to refute, but
despite their being advocated by many philosophers and physicists since
Minkowski, I do not believe that they should be the only coherent
metaphysical systems on offer. In chapter
8 it will be seen that alternatives can be devised that not only have more
explanatory power (e.g. for quantum physics, as in chapter
10),
but also more practical use (see below, end of this section). Once these
alternatives have been formulated, we should be able to judge in which way
our world is most adequately described.
Rejecting the objection (d), however, does not mean rejecting
all talk of the spacetime continuum. One alternative approach (following
Maxwell [1968, 1985 §5 & 6]) says that it is facts about objects,
rather than objects themselves, that are (or can construed to be) spread
out in time. Spatial relations are between objects, but temporal relations
are between facts about objects.
Another view follows Whitehead in regarding the spacetime continuum as
giving the ordering of possible events (even before there are any actual
events). This prospect will be further examined in chapter
8.
It does in any case seem very odd to deny that objects have dispositional
properties that relate what might happen as well as what actually happens.
To deny causes apart from their manifestations, Mellor [1974 p. 173]
shows, leads to some bizarre consequences, for then a disposition could not
be ascribed when its operation is impossible. Taking precautions to
avoid the conditions in which nuclear fuel would explode, to use his
example, should not mean that the fuel was not explosive. `It is
ridiculous to say that their success robs the fuel of its explosive
disposition and thus the precautions of their point.'
Furthermore, a theory that only predicted what actually happens, and not
what might happen, would be useless as an engineering planning tool. For
it would not be able to predict the consequences of a plan that we might
consider employing, but in the end did not actually use. Such a theory
could not tell us, for example, what would have happened if one of the
unsuccessful channel-tunnel designs had been chosen. These
questions are of great practical (and political) importance, and, as we
shall see in the next chapter, real physical theories are of course most
useful here.
Next: 2.4 Scientific Explanation of
Up: 2. Dispositions
Previous: 2.2 Derivative Dispositions
Prof Ian Thompson
2003-02-25
|